Aristotle's Principle of Non-Contradiction (PNC for short)
Summary of Stanford Encyclopedia Article's main points
- three versions of the principle of non-contradiction
- semantic (i.e. about truth and statements)
- opposite assertions
cannot be true at the same time (Metaph IV 6
1011b13–20)
- doxastic (i.e. about our beliefs)
- It is impossible to hold
(suppose) the same thing to be and not to be
(Metaph IV 3 1005b24 cf.1005b29–30)
- Seems to say that it is impossible to hold the same thing
to be F and not to be F.
- But many people have many contradictory beliefs.
- what a man says he
does not necessarily believe (Metaph IV 3
1005b23–26)
- Alternatively, this is a normative claim: one should not hold the
same thing to be F and not to be F.
- one cannot rationally hold the same thing to be F and
not-F.
- ontological (i.e. about what exists)
- This is the main
version of the principle
- It is impossible for the
same thing to belong and not to belong at the same time to
the same thing and in the same respect
(Metaph IV 3 1005b19–20).
- with the appropriate qualifications: The “same thing” that
belongs must be one and the same thing and it must be the
actual thing and not merely its linguistic expression. Also,
the thing that belongs must belong actually, and not merely
potentially, to its bearer.
- Which version Aristotle intends to establish is a matter of
controversy.
- PNC cannot be proven, but there are some very strong
indications that it is right:
- Aristotle says that without it, we could not do many things:
- we could not demarcate the subject matter of any of the
special sciences,
- we would not be able to distinguish between what something
is, for example a human being or a rabbit, and what it is
like, for example pale or white.
- Aristotle's own distinction between essence and accident
would be impossible to draw
- the inability to draw distinctions in general would make
rational discussion impossible
- So there are indirect indications that it is right.
- Could an opponent claim that PNC works in most areas, but
not all?
- Where does Aristotle talk about it?
- Metaphysics IV (Gamma) 3–6, especially 4
- BY FAR the most important discussion
- in De Interpretatione
- chapter 11 of Posterior Analytics I
- Where is the PNC in Aristotle's system
- In the Metaphysics:
it is part of the study of being qua being
- How it belongs there is a matter of some controversy: it
does not seem obvious that it belongs there
- But also one must admit that it does not seem obvious that
it does not belong there.
- It is a "common axiom"
- Common to what? to all the special sciences (i.e. biology,
mathematics, geology, etc.)
- but it is also common to the science of being qua being:
no science can prove PNC: it is indemonstrable
- axiom? it is not demonstrable and so is at the bedrock of
any science
- if it were demonstrable, the premises of that
demonstration would be more basic
- also, it cannot be demonstrated because every
demonstration relies on its being right
- you cannot prove it is right by assuming it is right
- that would be "begging the question"
- you cannot perform a reductio ad absurdum,
which would have one suppose for a moment that it is
wrong and then see what happens, because "seeing what
happens" involves assuming that it is right!
- It has no specific subject matter: it applies to everything
that is (the ontological version) as well as to everything one
thinks or imagines (doxastic version).
- Is it prior to truth, reference and identity?
- it assumes identity: it cannot be formulated without
it: "one and the same thing" involves identity
- this is pushing the Aristotelian envelope: that never
stops scholars
- Refuting those who deny the PNC
- Although it cannot be demonstrated, those who deny it can be
refuted on their own terms.
- "opponent" says that some claim is the case.
- "opponent" also agrees that a couple other things are the
case.
- But the other things conflict with the first claim.
- So "opponent" is inconsistent and must give up either the
original claim or some of the subsequent claims.
- Aristotle is trying to show that the opponent of the PNC is
committed to one thing that is not contradictory.
- The opponent is not bothered by inconsistency: they deny
PNC.
- Aristotle assumes his opponent takes the very strong
position that for any
x and for any
F, it is possible that F belongs to and does not belong to x
at the same time in the same respect.
- Aristotle wants to draw the opponent into saying
something, without making a complete statement, that shows
that he does accept that x is F and is not at the same
time not F
- Aristotle seems to be arguing that the world conforms to
PNC, or that PNC is true, because it is presupposed by and
explains the opponent's ability to say something
significant.
- Aristotle may be aiming to show that the ontological
version of the principle of non-contradiction is true, or he
may be aiming to show merely that it cannot be disbelieved
- Aristotle's challenge to his opponent:
- signify some one thing to both herself and another person.
- in other words, communicate just one thing: pick out one
object, "dog" or "man" for instance.
- if the communication works (i.e. if the person
communicating and the person being communicated with both
understand the same thing), then Aristotle thinks the
opponent is committed to PNC in at least one instance.
- Aristotle is showing the opponent that if she wants to
reject PNC she must:
- pick out the same object (e.g. "human being" or "dog")
twice and say that contradictory predicates apply to it
- if she does not mean anything definite by “human being”,
for example, then she will be unable to twice pick out a
subject of predication, for example, a human being, and
say that contradictory predicates apply.
- opponents cannot have any one thing to which accidents are
attributed
- Aristotle's "substance" and "essence" serves to provide
the thing to which accidents adhere
- those who deny PNC cannot have such a thing to hold
accidents together: they claim that every x is F and is not
F.
- thus they cannot have "substance"
- the idea is that it makes no sense to say the "pale" is
"musical"
- you have to say the pale "thing" is also a musical
"thing": and that requires a "thing" that just is that
thing (and not not that thing)
- it also makes no sense to say that Jacques is just a
bundle of accidents: without some unifying factor to make
them all "Jacques," they are just a heap of accidents
without unity: that unifying factor must make them one thing
and not not one thing.
- What if opponent refuses to take the challenge?
- opponent is no better than a vegetable
- both in that Aristotle cannot talk to a vegetable and in
that the opponent cannot show that she is not a vegetable
- even if opponent refuses to try to communicate, she must
still act, and action involves commitment to the claim that
something in the world is x and not not-x.
- opponent might reply that she can act "as if" there are
things in the world that are what they are and are not
what they are not.
- in that case, all Aristotle shows is that we have to act
"as if" PNC is correct. That is something.
- but Aristotle obviously wants more
- can he have more?
- maybe all we ever do is act "as if"
- Aristotle claims that rejecting PNC involves rejecting
anything that plays the role of making it the case that we can
reliably communicate AND also involves rejecting any
metaphysical analysis of things in the world that makes it the
case that things are just what they are and not simultaneously
not what they are.
- At the end of Metaphysics IV.4,
Aristotle
says:
- However much all things
may be so and not so, still there is a more and a less in
the nature of things; for we should not say that two and
three are equally even, nor is he who thinks four things
are five equally wrong with him who thinks they are a
thousand. If then they are not equally wrong, obviously
one is less wrong and therefore more right. If then that
which has more of any quality is nearer to it, there must
be some truth to which the more true is nearer.
- Aristotle never works it out, but what about a world in
which our views are mere approximations of truth, and even if
they happen to be the truth, we cannot be certain of that?
could there be a "fuzzy" or "vague" essentialism?
- Aristotle's confused opponents:
- In Metaphysics
IV.5, Aristotle talks about opponents who see a thing changing
and conclude from their observations of change that the same
thing must have had contrary properties: contrary properties
come into existence out of the same thing.
- Here, Aristotle introduces the distinction between
potential and actual.
- X can be both potentially F and actually not-F
- but X cannot be both actually F and actually not-F.
- and X cannot be both potentially F and not potentially F
- but it can be both potentially F and potentially not-F.
- Other opponents had a problem because of conflicting
appearances (the following is verbatim from the Stanf. Enc. of
Phil.):
- There are three sorts of cases of conflicting appearances:
- Things appear different to different members of the same
species, e.g., the same thing is thought bitter by some
and sweet by others (Metaph IV 5 1009b2–3).
- Things appear different to members of different species
(e.g., to other animals and to us) (Metaph IV 5 1009b7–8).
- Things do not always appear the same even to the senses
of the same individual (Metaph IV 5 1009b8–9).
- It is not clear which appearances are true and which false
(Metaph IV 5 1009b10).
- Conclusions:
- Nothing is true (Democritus in dogmatic mood, Metaph IV
5 1009b11–12).
- (If something is true) a true thing is not clear to us
(Democritus in skeptical mood, Metaph IV 5 1009b12).
- Everything is just as true as everything else. (This is
mentioned as an explanation of premise 2 at Metaph IV 5
1009b10–11. It is Protagoras's view, as described at the
beginning of Metaph. IV 5.)
- Aristotle agrees with 1
- Aristotle disagrees with 2: he does not think that people
are really confused about which appearances are right in
cases of conflicting appearances:
- they trust experts
- they trust their senses for things each sense is
authoritative about
- many moderns take conflicting appearances seriously,
especially in ethics.
- Another set of opponents are "Protagoras, Heraclitus, and
Theaetetus," who are characters in Plato's dialogue Theaetetus
- In Metaphysics IV
5, Aristotle mentions Protagoras' doctrine that each
individual human being is the measure of all things.
- PLATONIC detour
- At Theaetetus
151–183, Plato argues that Theaetetus, who holds that
knowledge is nothing but perception, is committed to
Protagoras's view via an argument from conflicting
appearances. If the wind appears cold to you but hot to me
and knowledge is nothing but perception, then we must both
be correct, as Protagoras says.
- Plato argues that Protagoras is committed to the view
that nothing is anything in itself (otherwise one might
be wrong about how it really is) and to a “secret”
Heraclitean doctrine of flux. In order to accommodate
more and more conflicting appearances, and to avoid
violating PNC, more and more flux is needed, until we
reach a radical version of Heraclitus's doctrine
according to which everything is “so and not so” (Tht
183), with accompanying difficulties for ordinary
language. The extended argument also contains a
mini-argument, a “self-refutation”, where Plato draws
the “exquisite” conclusion that Protagoras refutes
himself if he agrees that other people disagree with his
own view (Tht 171A-D). If they are right, then he must
be wrong!
- end of Platonic detour
- elements of Plato's discussion re-surface in Aristotle's
Metaphysics IV.
- Protagoras's view and the suggestion that everything is
“so and not so” go hand in hand.
- Heraclitus's followers thought that there is so much
change in the world that it is impossible to say anything
true, and so Cratylus, one of their number, was reduced to
wagging his finger.
- At the end of chapter 6, Aristotle concludes, “Let this, then
suffice to show (1) that the firmest belief is that opposite
assertions are not true at the same time, (2) what happens to
those who speak in this way and (3) why people do speak in this
way (Metaph IV 6 1011b13–15). ”
- On the first point, as we saw, it is controversial whether
Aristotle's conclusion that the firmest belief is a belief in
PNC carries with it the presupposition that PNC is true, a
presupposition that is needed for his own project of first
philosophy.
- On the second point, Aristotle shows that those who say that
they reject PNC do not really do so, or, if they do, they will
be giving up intelligible discourse and action, and—one might
add—they will be living in a world of mere sophistry and
power.
- On the third point, Aristotle discusses views about
perception and change that lead people to say that they reject
PNC.
- It is controversial how much of an essentialist or indeed
realist view one must accept if one accepts PNC, but it is
clear that PNC is essential for the project of an Aristotelian
science.
- Without it, Aristotle notes, beginners in philosophy who are
interested in the truth would be off on a wild goose chase
(Metaph VI 5 1009b36–8).