Aristotle Metaphysics IV4
1007a21-1007b18
- First, know that in order for us to understand Aristotle's
argument here, we must back up at least to 1006a1 and understand
a bit of the context. Please go read that at your leisure. You
needn't understand every bit, but it will provide some context.
- Aristotle is discussing people who, when asked "what is this?"
(pointing to a man), answer "It is a man" but also "It is not a
man." Why would they answer both of those things? Because they
think that "it is a musical thing" and "it is a be-trousered
thing" and "it is a hairy thing" etc. and NONE of those things
are identical to "being a man." Therefore, "it is a man and it
is not a man" is an answer that they think is right (Aristotle
disagrees). Aristotle wants to show that such people cannot
possibly be coherent or successfully refer to anything without
contradicting themselves in a way that they themselves must
agree is a contradiction (they won't admit right off that "it is
a man and it is not a man" is a contradiction). Along the
way, in the following paragraph, Aristotle argues that things
are not just associations of accidental properties: there must
be something that an accident is an accident of, and that cannot
be merely another accident. He is arguing that there must be
essences (which amounts to the same thing as saying that there
must be substances, he thinks).
- And in general those who use
this argument do away with substance and essence. For they
must say that all attributes are accident, and that there is
no such thing as being essentially man or animal. For if there
is to be any such thing as being essentially man, this will
not be being not-man or not being man (yet these are negations
of it); for there was some one thing which it meant, and this
was the substance of something. And denoting the substance of
a thing means that the essence of the thing is nothing else.
But if its being essentially man is to be the same as either
being essentially not-man or essentially not being man, then
its essence will be
something else. Therefore our opponents must say that there
cannot be such a definition of anything, but that all
attributes are accidental; for this is the distinction between
substance and accident--white is accidental to man, because
though he is white, whiteness is not his essence. But if all statements are accidental, there
will be nothing primary about which they are made, if the
accidental always implies predication about a subject. The
predication, then , must go on ad infinitum. But this is impossible; for not
even more than two terms can be combined. For an accident is
not an accident of an accident, unless it be because both are
accidents of the same subject. I mean, for instance, the white
is musical and the latter is white, only because both are
accidental to man. But Socrates is musical, not in this sense,
that both terms are accidental to something else. Since then
some predicates are accidental in this and some in that sense,
those which are accidental in the latter sense, in which white
is accidental to Socrates, cannot form an infinite series in
the upward direction--e.g. Socrates the white has not yet
another accident; for no unity can be got out of such a sum.
Nor again will white have another term accidental to it, e.g.
musical. For this is no more accidental to that than that is
to this; and at the same time we have drawn the distinction,
that while some predicates are accidental in this sense,
others are so in the sense in which musical is accidental to
Socrates; and the accident is an accident of an accident not
in cases of the latter kind, but only in cases of the other
kind, so that not all
terms will be accidental. There must, then, even in this case
be something that denotes substance. And it has been shown
that, if this is so, contradictories cannot be predicated at
the same time.