VERY CURSORY Notes on R.J Hankinson, chapter 4 of the Cambridge Companion to Aristotle
Aristotle has a strong idea of what constitutes
scientific knowledge: it must be able to take the form of
explanatory syllogisms, preferably Barbara's (AaB, BaC, therefore
AaC). What is more, Aristotle held that for such a syllogism to
express scientific knowledge, the premisses must be necessary.
To have scientific knowledge of X, you must not merely hold that X
is true. You must also be able to explain why it is the case. Thus
thinking that humans are mortal is not scientific knowledge unless
you also can explain why: because they are animals, and all animals
are mortal. But even that is not quite enough: you might say that
humans are mortal, because they are mammals, and all mammals are
mortal. That would be valid and sound, but not scientific, because
'mammal' is not the highest level in the genus-species hierarchy of
which "mortal" is a property. You must use the highest level in the
hierarchy to which the property applies.
What is more, you must be aware of the causal direction. Both of the
following syllogisms are valid and sound (according to Aristotle):
- All broad-leaved trees are deciduous;
- Vines are broad-leaved;
- Thus vines are deciduous.
- All deciduous trees are broad-leaved;
- Vines are deciduous;
- Thus vines are broad-leaved.
Only one of the above is explanatory according to Aristotle, namely
A (being broad-leaved causes being deciduous, but not vice versa).
But it is not yet fully scientific, because :
- All sap-coagulators are deciduous (that is the definition
of deciduous);
- All broad-leaved trees are sap-coagulators;
- Thus all broad-leaved trees are deciduous.
C justifies A1, and so C is more fully explanatory.
So, from Posterior Analytics,
it looks as if Aristotle wants scientific inquiry to consist of the
construction of explanatory syllogisms within certain constraints.
But the scientific treatises we have by Aristotle rarely, if ever,
exhibit that form. It is unclear what that means.
Perhaps in the Posterior
Analytics he is sketching an ideal structure that he simply
did not use in the down and in the dirt investigations that he
undertook.
A further problem is that Aristotle held that in the sublunary world
(i.e. on Earth itself, not orbiting Earth or further out in space),
generalities about substances tend to hold only for the most part.
While certain logical syllogism do work with "for the most part"
premisses, others do not: "Most Catholics are encouraged to marry;
all Carmelites are Catholics; so ... (nothing true results)".
Perhaps Aristotle held that once science advances far enough,
for-the-most-part premisses will be eliminated and replaced with
more fine-grained universal premises (e.g., "All Catholics who have
not taken celibacy vows are encouraged to marry"), but he nowhere
explicitly pursues that possibility. What is more, that possibility
is probably a dead end for him: he held that the reason why things
occur only for the most part is because they involve matter. Matter
somehow resists form, and so there will always be times when
the form-matter composite will fail. In such cases, there will be no
general explanation: rather, each particular case will have a
particular reason. Hence for-the-most-part premisses are not
eliminable.
Aristotle is not concerned with particular accounts of what causes
some event (e.g. So-and-so died by violence because he went out. He
went out because he was thirsty. He was thirsty because he ate spicy
food. He ate spicy food because ... etc.). That, for him, is not a
scientific explanation: he wants general explanation. It is simply
not the case that generally people who go out die by violence, nor
that people who are thirsty go out. It might be a general
explanation of thirst to say that eating spicy food causes thirst.
But the point is that Aristotle is simply not concerned with
particular explanation of particular happenings: he wants general
explanations. For something to be 'science,' he wants to know about
things that generally run through the structure of the world and its
changes.
What he needs, but does not have, is statistics and big data!
Aristotle addresses the following situations: I happen to be at the
well when the robbers are there, and so something happens, but it
was chance that I was there when the robbers were. No general
explanation is possible. A. says that chance caused the thing to
happen, and there is no further causal history to chance. One aspect
of this is that A. says that chance events have no final causes,
although they can have one in a sense (if craft could have led to
the result, Aristotle calls it chance that is a sort of final cause:
if craft could not have, then he calls it chance). An example: if I
happen on treasure while ploughing my garden, then "digging for
treasure" is the accidental final
cause of my finding it.