- Aristotle Nicomachean
Ethics
1.1 1094a1ff)
- Every art and every
inquiry,
and similarly every action and
choice, is thought to aim at some good; and for this reason
the good
has rightly been declared to be that at which all things
aim. But a
certain difference is found among ends; some are activities,
others are
products apart from the activities that produce them. Where
there are
ends apart from the actions, it is the nature of the
products to be
better than the activities. Now, as there are many actions,
arts, and
sciences, their ends also are many; the end of the medical
art is
health, that of shipbuilding a vessel, that of strategy
victory, that
of economics wealth. But where such arts fall under a single
capacity--as bridle-making and the other arts
concerned with the
equipment of horses fall under the art of riding, and this
and every
military action under strategy, in the same way other arts
fall under
yet others--in all of these the ends of the master arts are
to be
preferred to all the subordinate ends; for it is for the
sake of the
former that the latter are pursued. It makes no difference
whether the
activities themselves are the ends of the actions, or
something else
apart from the activitities , as in the case of the sciences
just
mentioned.
- What is the good?
- It is the aim of arts, inquiries, actions, and choices.
- As such, it is a goal
- Thus our actions, inquiries, arts, and choices are
teleologically arranged
- Which is better, the action/thing or the goal?
- Sometimes actions and their goals are separate
- a house is different from housebuilding
- the house is better than the action.
- Some arts, sciences, and actions are subordinate to
others
- carpentry is subordinate to building, as is plumbing,
etc.
- in such cases, the "master" art is better than its
subordinate arts or their ends
- because we pursue the subordinate things for the
sake of
the master things.
- There are some arts where the action and the product are
not
separate things: dancing, singing, and virtue are
examples.
- But we can still separate them conceptually?
- If, then, there is some
end
of the things we do, which we
desire for its own sake (everything else being desired for
the sake of
this), and if we do not choose everything for the sake of
something
else (for at that rate the process would go on to infinity,
so that our
desire would be empty and vain), clearly this must be the
good and the
chief good. Will not the knowledge of it, then, have a great
influence
on life? Shall we not, like archers who have a mark to aim
at, be more
likely to hit upon what we should? If so, we must try, in
outline at
least, to determine what it is, and of which of the sciences
or
capacities it is the object. It would seem to belong to the
most
authoritatitve art and that which is most truly the master
art. And
politics appears to be of this nature; for it is this that
ordains
which of the sciences should be studied in a state, and
which each
class of citizens should learn and up to what point they
should learn
them; and we see even the most highly esteemed of capacities
to fall
under this, e.g. strategy, economics, rhetoric; now, since
politics
uses the rest of the sciences, and since, again, it
legislates as to
what we are to do and what we are to abstain from, the end
of this
science must include those of the others, so that this end
must be the
good for man. For even if the end is the same for a single
man and for
a state, that of the state seems at all events something
greater and
more complete both to attain and to preserve; for though it
is worth
while to attain the end merely for one man, it is finer and
more
godlike to attain it for a nation or for city-states. These,
then, are
the ends at which our inquiry, being concerned with
politics, aims.
- Is there a master goal of a human life?
- If there is no thing that we desire purely for its own
sake, we could be stuck in an infinite process:
- we will choose X for the sake of Y, which will be
choosen
for the sake of Z, which will be chosen for the sake of
A, which will
be chosen for the sake of B, etc.
- either it will go on forever or loop back on itself.
- in either case, it will be infinite, which would make
our
desires "empty and vain."
- Aristotle seems to think that that is enough to
reject
the idea
- why? perhaps our desires simply are empty and vain.
- or perhaps it's like shampoo: lather, rinse, repeat
- and why is that empty and vain?
- presumably because it does not reach a goal: can't
he value process? maybe it does have a goal...
- But IF there is some thing we do for its own sake, it
would
be of practical use to know what it is.
- We can aim at it.
- Politics is the art that is the master art:
- it uses all the other sciences and arts and says
what
we are to do and not do
- thus it includes the ends of all the subordinate
arts
- and its end must be good
- politics is superior to ethics because it aims at
the
goal of a nation, not just an individual
- We'll have to see more about what A has to say
about
this in the Politics
and
elsewhere, because this seems like a dangerous
principle.
- In any case, we can see that A calls his inquiry here
politics, EVEN THOUGH the Nicomachean
Ethics concerns it self with
individuals.
- We also see him making a very controversial perhaps
nefarious claim that the good of the nation is finer and
more godlike than that of an individual.
- why possibly nefarious? because privileging the
state over individuals is problematic and a key
component of authoritarianism, totalitarianism,
fascism and other things that usually have a bad rap
in the US.
- Our discussion will be
adequate if it has as much clearness as
the subject matter admits of; for precision is not to be
sought for
alike in all discussions, any more than in all the products
of the
crafts. Now fine and just actions, which political science
investigates, exhibit much variety and fluctuation so that
they may be
thought to exist only by convention, and not by nature. And
goods also
exhibit similar fluctuation because they bring harm to many
people; for
before now men have been undone by reason of their wealth
and others by
reason of their courage. We must be content, then in
speaking of such
subjects and with such premisses to indicate the truth
roughly and in
outline, and in speaking about things which are only for the
most part
true and with premisses of the same kind to reach
conclusions that are
no better. In the same spirit, therefore, should each of our
statements
be received; for it is the mark of an educated man to look
for
precision in each class of things just so far as the nature
of the
subject admits; it is evidently equally foolish to accept
probable
reckoning from a mathematician and to demand from a
rhetorician
demonstrative proofs.
- An important principle: conclusions can be no more precise
than the subject matter allows
- How to apply it here, however, is a good question.
- Is this meant to mean that we need to round off our
calculations as we do in mathematics? If we have vague
input, we cannot
get output more precise than the input?
- Is this something like proto-statistics: what we say
here
applies to the generic human, but there is no actual
generic human,
only particular humans, and so what we say here is
theoretical and has
questionable practical application to any given
individual? or is limited by not dealing with the
particulars of a particular person (and, after all, we
are all particular people)?
- ...
- Let us resume our inquiry
and
state, in view of the fact that
all knowledge and choice aims at some good, what it is that
we say
political science aims at and what is the highest of all
goods
achievable by actions. Verbally there is very general
agreement; for
both the general run of men and people of superior
refinement say that
it is happiness, and identify living well and faring well
with being
happy; but with regard to what happiness is they differ, and
the many
do not give the same account as the wise. For the former
think it is
some plain and obvious thing, like pleasure, wealth, or
honor; they
differ, however, from one another--and often even the same
man
identifies it with different things, with health when he is
ill, with
wealth when he is poor; but, conscious of their ignorance,
they admire
those who proclaim some great thing that is above their
comprehension.
Now some thought that apart from these many goods there is
another
which is good in itself and causes the goodness of all these
as well.
To examine all the opinions that have been held would no
doubt be
somewhat fruitless; it is enough to examine those that are
most
prevalent or that seem to have some reason in their favor.
- First, we can agree on a name: we'll call the goal
happiness.
- But we all know that English "happiness" won't work, so
we
can't really even agree on a name...
- "Flourishing," "Well-being," "Human flourishing, " ...
- eudaimonia?
- Endoxa:
- various people think the goal is:
- pleasure
- wealth
- honor
- health
- many think it varies over time:
- health when I am sick
- wealth when I am poor
- others proclaim some grand thing beyond comprehension
- sort of like Aristotle is doing?
- perhaps like Plato's 'form of the good' which can seem
mystifying, but see next item
- others say that "good" is some thing separate from all
good
things: these are the Platonists.
- Let us not fail to notice,
however, that there is a difference
between arguments from and to first principles....while we
must begin
with what is familiar, things are so in two ways--some to
us, some
without qualification. Presumably, then, we must begin with
things
familiar to us. Hence any one who is to listen intelligently
to
lectures about what is noble and just and, generally, about
the
subjects of political science must have been brought up in
good habits.
For the facts are the starting-point, and if they are
sufficiently
plain to him, he will not need the reason as well. and the
man who has
been well brought up has or can easily get starting points...
- We have to start with what we think we know (whether it is
really knowable or not will, it is hoped, emerge)
- But if the inquiry is to reach what is knowable simpliciter, we have to
start out
with "good habits"
- in other words, A's ethics will only work for people who
already have good upbringing!
- it won't work so well for nazis, serial murderers,
homophobes, sexists, racists, etc.?
- or does this mean it won't work so well for slaves,
the poor, non-Greeks, deviants, etc.?
- What are we to make of this?
- Does it mean that the Ethics is simply dialectical:
that
it works from what we think we know forward, but cannot
work from what
is really knowable as a demonstrative science does?
- Aristotle does not seem to think that that is the
case.
- Surely here he is simply saying that for his intended
audience, the proper starting point is dialectical. It
will help them
to see the first principles when they come into view.
The right
starting points are helpful, because Aristotle does not
need to argue
for them. He does seem to say that there is a reason for
them.