Physics 2.3 (194b17-195a4)
Aristotle's four causes
- First off, Aristotle's 4 "causes" are not all causes in the
way that most modern English speakers think of causes.
- For Aristotle, science = causal knowledge
- Thus knowledge of what causes are is essential for every
science
- we think we have knowledge
of a thing only when we have grasped its cause
(APost. 71 b 9-11. Cf. APost. 94 a 20)
- we think we do not have
knowledge of a thing until we have grasped its why, that is
to say, its cause (Phys. 194 b 17-20)
- Aristotle's "causes" are often better thought of as
"explanations" or "reasons."
- Take any single thing, then ask yourself four questions:
- What is it made of?
- What made it/what action/what trigger led to its
creation/coming to be/happening/becoming what it is?
- What is it: shape, structure, arrangement? What makes it one
sort of thing rather than another? What holds it together?
What about the way it is put together makes it work?
- What is it for? What end is it likely to serve? What goal is
it likely to reach?
- Those four questions correspond to Aristotle's four causes:
- Material cause: "that out of which" it is made.
- Efficient Cause: the source of the objects
principle of change or stability.
- Formal Cause: the essence of the object.
- Final Cause: the
end/goal of the object, or what the object is good for.
- A note about final causes: they always presuppose the
formal cause: in order to explain the goal/purpose/end, you
must use the formal cause.
- Each of those four questions leads to a different sort of
explanation of the thing.
- The material cause:
“that out of which”, e.g., the bronze of a statue, the letters
of a syllable.
- The formal cause:
“the form”, “the account of what-it-is-to-be”, e.g., the shape
of a statue, the arrangement of a syllable, the functional
structure of a machine or an organism.
- The efficient
cause: “the primary source of the change or rest”, e.g., the
artisan, the art of bronze-casting the statue, the man who
gives advice, the father of the child.
- The final cause:
“the end, that for the sake of which a thing is done”, e.g.,
health is the end of the following things: walking, losing
weight, purging, drugs, and surgical tools.
- Take a statue:
- Its material
explains its existence: a bronze statue is a certain sort of
thing, and its material constituents, the elements that make
up bronze, cause it to have certain properties and explain a
lot about it.
- Some qualities of bronze are important for the statue-ness
of the statue. Others are not. Those that are important explain the statue and
are the material cause.
- bronze is also the subject of change, that is, the thing
that undergoes the change and results in a statue.
- art of bronze casting in the artisan = efficient cause or the
principle that produces the statue (Phys. 195 a 6-8. Cf.
Metaph. 1013 b 6-9).
- the artisan manifests specific knowledge, which is the
salient explanatory factor that one should pick as the most
accurate specification of the efficient cause (Phys. 195 b
21-25).
- this knowledge is not dependent upon and does not make
reference to the desires, beliefs and intentions of the
individual artisan
- it helps us to understand what it takes to produce the
statue: what steps are required
- Its form explains its existence: it is not *just* a lump of
bronze, it also has a certain shape, structure, and
arrangement.
- can an explanation of this type be given without a reference
to the statue? no!
- Its purpose as a statue explains it: it is "to
commemorate," "to instantiate beauty," "to decorate," or
some combination of those or something else. The need for a
commemorative object, or the need to express beauty, or the
need for a decorative object can explain the statue.
- bronze is melted and poured in the wax cast. Both the
prior and the subsequent stage are for the sake of a
certain end, the production of the statue.
- Clearly the statue enters in the explanation of each step
of the artistic production as the final cause or that for the sake of which
everything is done.
- conceptually the efficient and the final cause can be
separated, but the formal and final causes are tightly
linked.
- By "final causes," Aristotle offers an explanation that
refers to the telos
or end of the process= a teleological
explanation
- teleological explanation does not necessarily depend upon
the application of psychological concepts such as desires,
beliefs and intentions. But if they are present, they are
often integral to the final cause, although it's possible
that they are merely accidental to whatever is the object of
explanation.
- Aristotle explains natural process on the basis of a
teleological model
- Causes, like primary substances, have what we can call species
and genera, and the species and genera of the cause are also
causes (we might call them secondary causes).
- The material cause of the statue, bronze,, is a particular
sort of matter whose genus is metal, and so metal is a
material cause of the statue.
- In somewhat modern terms, the material cause of our body is
organs, but organs are made up of something like tissue as their
matter,
and tissue is made up of cells as its matter, which are made up
of cellular organs as their matter, which are made up of plasms,
which are made up of molecules, which are made up of elements,
etc.
- all the way down this ladder, we may have mere matter
and most basic form.
- and the ladder gives us a genus-species-and-particular
ordering of the material cause of our body
- Causes also have coincidental properties/aspects, which are
coincidental causes.
- For instance, let us say that Joe the sculptor makes a
statue: Joe is the efficient cause of the statue. But Joe also
is a mountain climber, and so we might say that a mountain
climber is the efficient cause of the statue. If we are more
precise, we say that Joe's sculpting craft is the efficient
cause, and the other qualities of Joe, such as
mountain-climbing, are coincidental efficient causes.
- Aristotle's project with causes is scientific explanation
- thus he is interested in general causes for general
phenomena
- that is not to say he does not understand that particular
things have particular causes
- this statue is caused by this bronze, this
sculptor's skill, this form, and for this
end.
- Aristotle searches “for
general causes of general things and for particular causes
of particular things” (Phys. 195 a 25-26)
- idiosyncrasies that may be important in studying a
particular bronze statue as the great achievement of an
individual artisan are mostly extraneous to the more general
case of statues.
- Chance causes some things, as does luck.
- luck is a subset of chance (note that this is slightly
different terminology from that in our translation: I am using
"luck" for what was termed "chance" there): chance in an agent
is luck, whereas chance involving non-agents is just chance
- Only things that can act can be lucky.
- "Acting" is being confined to "agents" on this
terminology: a pebble is not an agent. A person is.
- Things that cannot act cannot be lucky, but can be affected
by chance.
- A pebble is affected by chance. A person is affected by
luck.
- An example of chance is coincidence: coincidence can be a
cause, but coincidences have no cause (Physics 2.4 ff.):
- A scenario: 10 people fall and hurt themselves on a single
day in a single building: no single thing is the cause of
those 10 falls (one falls because she wore very slippery shoes
and happened to step in a puddle of grease, another falls
because a man pushed her out of his way, another falls because
he had a heart attack, etc. The institution that owns the
building decides to radically overhaul their building to avoid
accidental falls BECAUSE of the coincidence of 10 falls, which
drew their attention to potential liability. But THERE IS NO
SINGLE CAUSE for those 10 falls all occurring in the same
building on the same day.
- Cf. Aristotle's man who ate spicy food, went to well, was
killed by brigands: no tight causal connection between spicy
food and being killed by brigands, but that is nonetheless why
the man was killed: bad luck.
- There is no direct cause of chance/luck, even though every
thing has a cause.
- In the scenario above, each accidental fall has its own
causes, and so you can explain all ten of those falls via
direct causes. What you cannot explain is why they all
happened on the same day: that is the coincidental part of the
scenario. But that coincidental part is what CAUSED the
institution that owns the building to revise its policies.
- ABOUT FINAL CAUSES
- Physics II 8 is
Aristotle's general defense of final causes.
- He needs to defend them because, he claims, his
predecessors believed only in efficient and material causes.
- His defence of final causes shows that there are aspects
of nature that cannot be explained by efficient and material
causes alone.
- Final causes, he claims, are the best explanation for
these aspects of nature.
- Aristotle holds, for example, that certain teeth have
certain shapes because of what they are for. Those of
carnivores are designed to tear and rip. Those of herbivores
are designed to crush (cf. Physics
198b24-27).
- "Final" causation is often referred to as "teleology," which
derives from Greek τελος "end, goal."
- Teleology is often thought of as requiring an agent
separate from the thing that has a final cause. For instance,
if an oak tree has a final cause, must there not be something
apart from the oak tree that uses the oak tree for some goal
or end?
- The ultimate result of many teleological views is that there
must be a God who designs the world: if things have a purpose,
whose purpose? If things have a design that makes them FOR
certain goals, there must be a designer.
- Aristotle would say that for us to have teleology, there is
no need for such a separate agent, no need for a designer. The
goal of the acorn is to become an oak tree. The acorn aims to
fully actualize the form of a full-grown oak tree, but is not
an agent, and no agent set it in motion. It is a "self-mover."
- A question to ask about teleology is whether it uses an
occurrence in the future to explain something that happens
now. If that is the case, how can we call it a cause? If the
thing that does the causing occurs AFTER the thing that is
caused, the normal relation of cause to caused is backwards.
- Well, what of it? Think of genes: they provide a sort of set
of instructions for the acorn to build itself. They cause the
oak to react to its environment in certain ways. They cause
the oak tree to produce more acorns (which is perhaps its
purpose). I see no need for god to enter the picture, and I
see no need for a future event to cause a present one there.
Can we characterize genes as involving final causes? I think
so. The final cause in nature is a potential within
things to become what they become.
- The Rain, for example:
- Phys 198b19-21
explains that it rains because of material processes:
warm air is drawn up and cools off and becomes water, which
comes down as rain.
- 198b21-23 explains that the crops may be nourished or
spoiled as a result of the rain, and yet it does not rain for
the sake of that result. It is a coincidence.
- Why is it not a coincidence that the front teeth grow sharp
for cutting, while the rear teeth are broad for grinding? When
the animal's teeth grow that way, it survives. When they do
not, it dies. Why not a coincidence? (198b23-27)
- Aristotle replies that he wants an explanation of why it is
a
regular occurrence that the teeth grow in such a way
that the animal survives. It is implausible that it is a
coincidence every time. Final causation is offered to explain
regularity.
- In some ways, it is just a bandaid: we want to know more
about how that works: Darwin offered a mechanism: does that
mechanism make final causes extraneous?
- Darwin's theory holds that natural selection works like a
giant filter: those traits that confer a reproductive or
survival advantage get thru the filter and so survive.
- Is this different from final causation?
- an advantage is toward some goal: there can't be an
advantage that is not for some goal
- the goal is primarily survival of the species and
secondarily survival of the individual
- it levels the goal of humanity and that of gnats and
protozoans: is that a problem for Aristotle?\perhaps
tertiarily there might be some favoring of "well-being"
and "development of potential" in that individuals who
are faring well are more likely to also mate and
reproduce?
- A house and an organism, for examples
- In de Partibus Animalium
(Parts of Animals),
Book I, Aristotle presents an argument for the priority of the
final cause over the efficient cause.
- Take a house:
- all the building materials are delivered
- they are necessary: without them a house cannot be built
- they are not sufficient: they will just sit there unless
there is something more
- the builder comes: the skill she has is an efficient cause
- but all of this is for the sake of a house: a house is the
final cause.
- from the very start, all is done with the house in view
as the goal
- without it, nothing happens
- Take an organism:
- Parts of Animals
640a18-19 says that "generation
is for the sake of substance, not substance for the sake
of generation"
- the proper way to explain the generation of an animal is
to begin with the end of the process, the adult full-grown
animal.
- when Empedocles explains the formation of the spine as the
result of some fetal behavior, Aristotle says that may be
part of the explanation, but it is insufficient:
- first off, the fetus had to have the power to move, so
that must be part of the explanation
- furthermore, the spine is for-the-sake of support of an
adult human's weight. That must be part of the explanation
as well.
- procreation and causality
- Aristotle maintained that something that is in motion
requires an efficient cause not just to set it in motion, but
also to keep it in motion.
- Aristotle had no concept of inertia!!!
- also no concept of causation at a distance (gravity,
magnetism, etc.)
- For Aristotle, efficient causation required contact, and
that contact had to occur as long as the caused thing was
changing/moving
- So what about procreation? see Generation of Animals I and II.
- animals procreate, because it is the closest they can get
to immortality (immortality is a goal because it would
involve permanent being, which would involve more full
actuality)
- males are superior: they contribute more form for the
human: they contribute the last thing that is necessary to
create a viable human (obviously Aristotle did not know what
we know)
- remember this is Aristotle: he was limited in some ways
by his environment and culture: nonetheless, as a
philosopher, he might/could/should have risen above those
limits. Could/should he have in this instance?
- females contribute menses, cooked-up blood that falls
short of human form: it is closer to human than earth, air,
fire, and water, but it falls short.
- The female residue
[menses] is potentially what the animal is by
nature, and it contains the parts potentially, although
not actually, and because when something active and
something passive come into contact ... the one
immediately acts and the other is acted upon in the
manner in which they are active and passive. And the
female provides the matter, the male the origin of the
change. (GA II4 740b19-25)
- active and passive is explained at Metaphysics Theta,
1046a4-18
- active and passive correspond to efficient and
material cause
- the male is the efficient cause, the source of the
change
- the female is material cause, the thing acted on
- the semen does its work, then evaporates!
- so what about the need for an efficient cause to
maintain contact while the change is taking place?
- does Aristotle think that the change to a human soul
takes place right away?
- What is sought now is
not the material out of which but the agency by which
the parts come to be. For either something outside them
makes them, or something which exists within the seed
and the semen; and whatever it is must either be a part
of soul or soul, or something which possesses soul. But
it seems unreasonable to suppose that anything outside
could create anything to do with the viscera, or any of
the other parts; for it cannot cause movement without
being in contact, and nothing can be affected by it
unless it causes movement. Therefore it must be
something which exists within the fetation, either as a
part of it or as distinct from it. (GA II1 733b32-734a6)
- in the case of things with natures, the nature operates
by permeating the material and operating from within, not
from without.
- the father's semen apparently causes a change to the
material, which thereby acquires a nature which works from
within.
- a materialist might hold that mechanical materialistic
explanations work for it all, but Aristotle rejects that
as too limited: Aristotle wants an explanation of the
organization of the growth of the human fetus.
- God and the final cause
- God, for Aristotle, is necessary, because there has to be
something which is purely actual. More on this elsewhere:
please accept for now that Aristotle thinks there must be
something that is pure actuality.
- God exists as pure actuality consisting in rational
contemplation of the best thing, god itself.
- God is the final cause of EVERYTHING
- everything aims to imitate God's perfect actuality
- everything seeks actuality, the fulfillment of its
potential, full being.
- this "aiming" or "seeking" need not be conscious,
involving beliefs, etc.:
- even the elements, earth, air, fire, and water, strive
to become fully actual, which would involve their
fulfilling their potential:
- each has its own proper place, which is part of its
goal.
- Causal explanation
- the best explanations will consist of all four causes, but
the formal and final will have priority over the efficient and
material.
- Aristotle realized that not everything has all 4 causes.
- An eclipse of the moon has no final cause (Metaphysics 1044b12)
- deprivation of light by the interposition of the earth
between the sun and the moon is the efficient cause
- there is no final cause
- Aristotle thought that the natural world has nisuses or
strivings within its members:
- acorns are simply aimed at becoming oaks
- human embryos are aimed at becoming adult humans
- thus he thinks that developmental biology is an
error-theory: the thing that needs to be explained is not
why things become what they do, but why in so many cases
they fail.
- common objection: Aristotle is just saying that things do
what they do because that is the sort of things they do.
- where's the explanation in that?
- reply:
- until we come up with a way to bridge the gap from a
mechanical/material explanation at the most basic
microscopic level (atoms? quarks? energy?) to the
macroscopic level (us, plants, mountains), there is a
point to asking what is different about the macroscopic
level
- Aristotle's theory sorts the world into natural kinds:
humans beget humans, plants beget plants. Certain things
come to be from certain things, and that has to do with
their form and their goal.
- if we believe DNA is the code of life, how far are we
from Aristotle? Think of it as a formula for local
decrease in entropy: that's what a "final goal" is: the
instructions for a local decrease in entropy: DNA is the
formula
- Also, Aristotle's theory contributes to our
understanding of how organisms work: the function of parts
and the relation to wholes. That's what final and formal
causes are about.
- Thus formal and final causes do a bit more work than
merely saying that things do what they do because that's
the sort of thing they do.
- Aristotle as historian of philosophy
- Aristotle begins the Metaphysics
with a survey of how his predecessors investigated causes
- this is part of Aristotle's typical procedure: phainomena,
endoxa, puzzles, then solutions.
- among the most important predecessors:
- Leucippus and Democritus developed ancient atomism: a
materialistic theory which posited atoms and void as the
basis of reality.
- Empedocles posited four elements: earth, air, fire,
and water, which can be compounded and dissolved by two
forces, Love and Strife
- Anaxagoras held that everything had the seeds
of everything else in it, but Mind directed it
all.
- Pythagoreans held that number imposed a limit or
structure on matter's indeterminacy.
- Plato held that there is material and formal
causation, according to Aristotle. Plato also held that
everything is arranged for the best, which is a sort of
teleology, but not like Aristotle's.
- Aristotle's comment:
- While all generation
and destruction may well be from one or more elements,
still why does this occur, and because of what cause (aition)? For it can't be that the
substrate moves itself. I mean for instance that
neither wood nor bronze are responsible (aitios) for each of their changes:
it's not the wood which makes the bed or the bronze the
statue, but something else is the cause of the change in
each case. To investigate this is to investigate the other cause, that from which
comes the origination of change. (Metaphysics A3 984a19-27)
- For neither earth nor
anything else of that sort seeem a likely cause of
things either being or becoming good and beautiful,
and nor did they seem so to them (Aristotle's
predecessors). Nor can it be right to
entrust such a matter to chance and fortune (Metaphysics A3
984b11-15)
- Aristotle was the first to engage in anything like a history
of philosophy, but it is not clear that he had any real
developed views on historical method, etc..
- But he is not an impartial historian.
- Aristotle's account of his predecessors is oriented almost
completely toward his own way of viewing causes: thus he
claims predecessors who have a different idea got it wrong or
missed crucial things.
- This situation is frustrating, because Aristotle's account
of his predecessors, especially those called
"Pre-Socratics," is often our best source for our own
knowledge of his predecessors: the Aristotelian lens
distorts their intentions and makes it difficult to see
their ideas clearly.
- Unfortunately, many people blame Aristotle for this. That
is unfair, because Aristotle was not trying to give a
disinterested account of his predecessors' thoughts. He is,
rather, trying to show that his ideas have a history, but
are new, different, and better in various ways.
- The fact that his account is often our best information
about his predecessors is not his fault. But it's still
frustrating, because we would really like to know more about
those predecessors.
- Texts of interest for Aristotelian causes
- Physics II.3 (general discussion of types of causes)
- Physics II.8 (final cause: has bits tantalizingly
close to evolutionary theory)
Good additional material: Cause of Persian War (hankinson P. 225-6),
stars twinkling (ibidem 225), antlers (ibidem 227).