CLAS 196/PHIL196
Stoicism
The Final End
Diogenes Laertius 7.87-88 (LIII in our website numbering)
On which account Zeno was
the first writer who, in his treatise on the Nature of Man, said, that the chief good was confessedly to live
according to nature; which is to live
according to virtue, for nature leads us to this
point. And in like manner Cleanthes speaks in his treatise on
Pleasure, and so do Posidonius and Hecaton in their essays on Ends
as the Chief Good. And again, to live according to virtue is the
same thing as living according to one’s experience of those things which
happen by nature; as
Chrysippus explains it in the first book of his treatise on
the Chief Good. For our individual
natures are all parts of universal nature; on which account the
chief good is to live
in a manner corresponding to nature, and that means
corresponding to one‘s own nature and to universal nature;
doing none of those things which the common law of mankind is in the
habit of forbidding, and that common law is identical with that
right reason which pervades everything, being the same with Jupiter,
who is the regulator and chief manager of all existing things.
Again, this very thing is the virtue of the happy man and the
perfect happiness of life when everything is done according to a
harmony with the genius of each individual with reference to the
will of the universal governor and manager of all things. Diogenes, accordingly, says expressly that the chief good is to act according to sound
reason in our selection of things according to our nature.
And Archidemus defines it to be living in the discharge of all becoming duties.
Chrysippus again understands that the nature, in a manner
corresponding to which we ought to live, is both the common nature,
and also human nature in particular; but Cleanthes will not admit of any other nature than the
common one alone, as that to which people ought to live in a
manner corresponding; and re- [293>] pudiates all mention of a
particular nature. And he asserts that virtue is a
disposition of the mind always consistent and always harmonious;
that one ought to seek it out for its own sake, without being
influenced by fear or hope by any external influence. Moreover, that
it is in it that happiness consists, as producing in the soul the
harmony of a life always consistent with itself; and that if a
rational animal goes the wrong way, it is because it allows itself
to be misled by the deceitful appearances of exterior things, or
perhaps by the instigation of those who surround it; for nature
herself never gives us any but good inclinations.
Stobaeus 2.75-76
Zeno represented the end as: "living in agreement".
This is living in accordance with
one concordant reason, since those who live in conflict are
unhappy. His successors expressed
this in a more expanded form, "living in agreement with nature",
since they took Zeno's statement
to be an incomplete predicate. Cleanthes, his first successor, added "with nature", and
represented it as follows: "the end is living in agreement with nature".
Chrysippus wanted to make this clearer and expressed it thus: "living in accordance with experience of
what happens by nature".
Cicero, de Finibus (on Ends) 3.31
We are left with the conclusion that the final good is a life in
which one applies knowledge
of those things that happen by nature, selecting those in accordance with nature and
rejecting those contrary to nature, that is, a life in agreement and consistent with
nature.
- Candidates for the telos
of life:
- One we might need to reject right away:
- "Living in agreement" in the sense of living a life that
is self-consistent: Brennan argues that it is shorthand
for "living in agreement with nature," both because the
Stoics said it was an incomplete predicate and because
normal Greek syntax agrees that it is incomplete.
- Some thinkers, however, believe it means "to live
consistently" and think that it is a candidate which later
Stoics rejected. They are most likely wrong that that is
what it is, says Brennan
- BUT, if you have faith that truth is always consistent
with truth, falsity is always inconsistent with at least
some truth, and falsity is always inconsistent with at
least some other falsity, then if you could discover an
entirely consistent system, you would think you were
justified in thinking you had discovered truth (and
truth is a necessary component to a kataleptic
impression, and an impression is a necessary component
to an impulse, and an impulse is necessary for action:
thus living consistently might in fact wind up being
"living in agreement with nature")
- Brennan claims, however, that having only consistent
beliefs does not necessarily mean that one will have
well-ordered beliefs or any system to one's beliefs.
Although strictly true, it is hard to see how this
would work in general and specifically with the
Stoics, who obviously strive for connected
understandings and explanations.
- AND we should bear in mind that those who champion
"living in agreement" as a real candidate for the
original Zenonian telos
are championing it in a different way. They claim,
namely, that it involves living in agreement with
oneself, and that according to it, agents would not need
to look outside themselves and their reason.
- Brennan thinks that living consistently would run the
risk of not being flexible enough: Stoics need to be
flexible enough to handle all the slings and arrows of
the unpredictable nature of human life.
- The telos should
be a predicate: it should be the sort of thing that can fill
the blank in an impulse: "It's a good/bad idea to _______":
remember that an impulse is assent to the combination of an
impression and its proposition. The proposition has an
evaluative judgement ("it would be good to..." or "one should
avoid ...") and a predicate term (kategorema) which specifies the action.
- The candidates:
- Zeno, Cleanthes, and Chrysippus all reportedly
formulated the telos
with reference to nature.
- to live in agreement with nature
- to live following nature
- to live according to the experience of what happens by
nature
- to live according to one's own nature and the nature
of the wholes.
- Diogenes of Babylon and Antipater of Tarsus reportedly
formulated the telos
with reference to selection:
- to reason well in the selection of things according to
nature
- to reason well in the selection and disselection of
things according to nature
- to live in the continual selection of things according
to nature and disselection of things contrary to nature
- Antipater also reportedly formulated it as:
- to do everything that is up to you, continually and
without deviation, in order to acquire the things that
are promoted by nature.
- Another formulation:
- to live according to virtue.
- These candidates have some attractiveness: saying that virtue
is a disposition to agree with what is according to nature and
that virtue is the only good provides a nice connection between
the telos and the
good.
- What of indifferents: Aristo or Aristotle
- Aristo, Zeno's student, said that all this talk of good and
indifferent had a fundamental problem:
- If the indifferents have no value, then there is no reason
to prefer one to the other, and thus there is no reason do
do anything.
- Chrysippus' response was that Aristo's argument made
virtue incomprehensible, for virtue's job is to help us
wisely choose between indifferents.
- Aristotle, on the other hand, included moderate good health,
food, means to live, etc. among goods. He said one cannot live
a happy fulfilled life without some of them. That is because,
e.g., health is good in and of itself and as an instrument,
wealth is good as an instrument, etc.
- Antiochus, whom we met in the notes on Brennan Chapter 8,
said that the Stoics cannot find any position between Aristo
and Aristotle: either the indifferents have some value or they
don't.
- If a choice can be justified for some other reason than
that it contributes toward the telos, then there is a problem in that the
telos is explicitly
said to be that for the sake of which all else is
done. If the telos
is good, and we make choices not based upon considerations
of the good, then we are not doing all else for the
sake of the good. Incoherence! At the heart of Stoicism?
- Plutarch formulates it well in On Common Conceptions, 1070f
- It is contrary to
the common conceptions that life should have two ends
or targets set before it and that all our actions
should not be referred to just one thing. But it is
still further contrary to the common conception that
the end should be one thing and the point of reference
for every action something else. Yet they, the Stoics
must stick to one of these alternatives.
- Brennan formulates the problem succinctly: it seems that one cannot
consistently hold the following:
- Our actions in life are rational only to the extent that
they are related to the final end;
- Only virtue is good; it alone is the final end and
reference point;
- It is rational to pursue things other than virtue, like
food and health.
- The Stoics clearly think that it is rational to select
indifferents, and yet they believe that indifferents are not
any part of the good and are not instruments useful to the
good, AND they also believe that it is rational to select
them even though actually getting them is a matter of
indifference.
- The Stoics think that a sage exercises reason and virtue
in every act of selection . Selection is done wisely,
temperately, courageously, etc.
- The act of selection is itself a manifestation and
exercise of the sage's virtue and hence rationality. By
choosing, sages use experience of nature to make their
actions conform to nature and thereby attain the end.
- HOW CAN THAT BE?
- Plutarch, On Common
Conceptions 1070f-1071e
- If someone were to say
that an archer does everything in his power not for the
sake of hitting the target but for the sake of doing
everything in his power, one would suppose him to be
speaking in a riddling and fantastic way. So it is with
the idiots who insist that the end of aiming at things
in accordance with nature is not the getting but the
taking and selecting of them, and that being healthy is
not each man's end in his desire and pursuit of health,
but on the contrary being healthy has reference to the
desire and pursuit of being healthy...
- For what is the
difference between someone's saying that health has come
into being for the sake of drugs, not drugs for the sake
of health, and one who makes the selection of drugs and
their composition and use more choiceworthy than health,
or rather regards health as not choiceworthy at all, but
locates the end in activity concerning the drugs, and
declares desire to be the end of the getting, not the
getting the end of the desire? "Yes, by Zeus, for
reasoning well and prudence are attributes of the
desire." That is fine, we shall say, if it views the
getting and possession of what it desires as related to
its end But if not, its reasoning well is destroyed,
since it does everything for the sake of getting what is
not important or a source of happiness to get.
- "What is so wise about pursuing things that don't
matter?" (Brennan, P. 145)
- Isn't it like the obsessive collector of rubber-bands?
There is nothing admirable or good about it.
- And wouldn't it be even worse if the rubber-band
collector said she did not care if she actually got any
rubber-bands?
- Remind you of fishing?
- The Stoic answer: it's like a game
- In games, the rules within the game justify all the
steps the players take: the goal is clear, and why they do
things is thus clear too.
- But games do not really matter: they simply have no
particular ethical content, good or bad.
- Epictetus, discourses
2.5
- Things themselves are
indifferent; but the use of them is not indifferent.
How then shall a man preserve firmness and
tranquility, and at the same time be careful and
neither rash nor negligent? If he imitates those who
play at dice. The counters are indifferent; the dice
are indifferent. How do I know what the cast will be?
But to use carefully and dexterously the cast of the
dice, this is my business. Thus in life also the chief business is this:
distinguish and separate things, and say, “Externals
are not in my power: will is in my power. Where
shall I seek the good and the bad? Within, in the
things which are my own.” But in what does not
belong to you call nothing either good or bad, or
profit or damage or anything of the kind.
“What then? Should we use such things
carelessly?” In no way: for this on the other hand
is bad for the faculty of the will, and consequently
against nature; but we should act carefully because
the use is not indifferent and we should also act
with firmness and freedom from perturbations because
the material is indifferent. For where the
material is not indifferent, there no man can hinder
me nor compel me. Where I can be hindered and
compelled the obtaining of those things is not in my
power, nor is it good or bad; but the use is either
bad or good, and the use is in my power. But it is
difficult to mingle and to bring together these two
things, the carefulness of him who is affected by the
matter and the firmness of him who has no regard for
it; but it is not impossible; and if it is, happiness
is impossible. But we
should act as we do in the case of a voyage. What
can I do? I can choose the master of the ship, the
sailors, the day, the opportunity. Then comes a
storm. What more have I to care for? for my part is
done. The business belongs to another—the
master. But the ship is sinking—what then have I to
do? I do the only things that I can, not to be drowned
full of fear, nor screaming, nor blaming God, but
knowing that what has been produced must also perish:
for I am not an immortal being, but a man, a part of
the whole, as an hour is a part of the day: I must be
present like the hour, and past like the hour. What
difference, then, does it make to me how I pass away,
whether by being suffocated or by a fever, for I must
pass through some such means?
This is just what you
will see those doing who play at ball skillfully. No one cares about the
ball being good or bad, but about throwing and
catching it. In this therefore is the skill, this
the art, the quickness, the judgement, so
that if I spread out my lap I may not be able to catch
it, and another, if I throw, may catch the ball. But
if with perturbation and fear we receive or throw the
ball, what kind of play is it then, and wherein shall
a man be steady, and how shall a man see the order in
the game? But one will say, “Throw”; or, “Do not
throw”; and another will say, “You have thrown once.”
This is quarreling, not play.
Socrates, then, knew
how to play at ball. How?” By using pleasantry in the
court where he was tried. “Tell me,” he says, “Anytus,
how do you say that I do not believe in God. The
Demons, who are they, think you? Are they not sons of
Gods, or compounded of gods and men?” When Anytus
admitted this, Socrates said, “Who then, think you,
can believe that there are mules, but not asses”; and
this he said as if he were playing at ball. And what
was the ball in that case? Life, chains, banishment, a
draught of poison, separation from wife and leaving
children orphans. These were the things with which he
was playing; but still he did play and threw the ball
skillfully. So we should do: we must employ all the
care of the players, but show the same indifference
about the ball. For we ought by all means to apply
our art to some external material, not as valuing
the material, but, whatever it may be, showing our
art in it.
- Epictetus offers us a model of how it can be rational to
take action concerning what one thinks is indifferent.
- Internal to the game, there are reasons and
justifications
- External to the game, those things are indifferent
- there simply is no particular ethical content to the
internal workings of a game (as long as the rules are
followed: breaking the rules seems to be another
matter, or even trying to break them)
- The relation between internal-to-the-game goals and
justifications and external-to-the-game goals and
justifications is not direct: losing (which has negative
value within the game) can build character (which has
positive value external to the game) and can be better
than winning, etc.
- One problem with this model, Brennan thinks, is that
games usually have value external to themselves: they are
entertainment, they foster skills useful elsewhere, etc.
- Thus games are parasitical on an external world
- the way that actions within a game "matter" is by
acting "as if" they are actions outside of the game
- so those who play the game as Stoics are supposed to
act "as if" it mattered, "as if" the goal of the game
is the good, while fully aware that it does not?
- usually, the value of activities within a game
derives from their crossover value and relation to
outside-of-the-game activities
- In terms of the analogy, the things within a game are
analogous to indifferents, and virtue is analogous to
what?
- the externally valuable things about a game: the
skills it builds, its entertainment value, it passes the
time, (anything else?)
- if the only justification for actions is internal to
the game, then there is no reason to do them that
corresponds to why a sage should do them.
- Brennan opts for a minimalist reading of the analogy:
- it simply shows that contrary to Plutarch's claims,
there are at least some situations where it is rational
to pursue things that are indifferent.
- The Stoics can offer answers as to why we should play
the game of indifferents:
- Zeus himself plays it: we are not important to him,
and yet his providence guides our world. We have good
reason to imitate God.
- Our nature is to relate to indifferents this way: we
are simply made BY NATURE to play this game.
- Wisdom and virtue need some sort of material to
manifest themselves in: why not these indifferents?
- just like art needs a material, but the material is
not the point: if it were, then we would admire the
materials of art, not the composition, structure,
lines, etc.
- we need an arena in which to act: virtue is a
quality of our actions that is independent on our
success at the rules of the indifferents game, but the
indifferents game is an arena in which virtue can
nonetheless manifest itself.
- BUT the game analogy does not provide or support those
answers: it merely shows that there exist situations in
which it is rational to engage with things that are
indifferent in and of themselves.
- SO don't push that analogy so far that it makes the
Stoic point incoherent, because forcing an analogy to fit
so tightly that it defeats what it is supposed to
illuminate is always a questionable move.
- The analogy has moved us a bit further forward toward
seeing how Stoicism makes sense: it has helped to move us
along toward a solution to the problem presented at the
beginning of this document. Once it stops doing that, we
should stop following it.