- Zeno's Paradoxes
- First off, let's get some distance from the particular
paradoxes.
- What is Zeno trying to do generally?
- Prove that Parmenides is right: everything is unified:
there is no movement, no time, no alteration
- Prove that reality is one thing, unchanging, and
indivisible.
- There is no part that is more or less real nor is there
more than one reality or truth or being
- As an aside, there are those who think that quantum
general relativity is on Parmenides' side: they are much
smarter than I and I cannot judge their arguments, but
it's interesting.
- Many people criticized Parmenides because what he claimed
seemed so preposterous
- Zeno wants to show that assuming that the world is the way
people claim is also absured
- Claiming that things move has absurd consequences
- Claiming that there are many things has absurd
consequences
- etc.
- Digression: Argument form:
- Ad absurdum:
- You claim one thing. You prove it by assuming the contrary
of that claim, just for the sake of argument. Then you show
that absurd, unacceptable, obviously false, or contradictory
results follow.
- You need light to see, otherwise you could see in the
dark.
- You have to brush your teeth, otherwise your teeth
will fall out.
- Ad hominem:
- an argument addressed to a particular position or a
particular person.
- In this case, the argument only really works against
that position or person, but may have huge flaws
otherwise.
- I can argue against racism by arguing that Zorgunthol's
particular racist theory is wrong: that is an ad hominem
argument.
- This is the sort Zeno uses: he is trying to take
people's own beliefs and defeat them. He is not
concerned with whether those beliefs are right or not.
- Another way to make an ad hominem argument is
less respectable: it is downright false
- You know nothing about fashion: just look at your
car.
- If your mother is such a good pool player, why does
she miss every basket she shoots?
- The argument that what they discharge into the
river is harmless is wrong: that company is a for
profit entity.
- who are you to say I stink: have you sniffed your
own shoes?
- Paradox.
- A paradox is what results from taking reasonable
assumptions and deducing a contradiction or unacceptable
consequence from them.
- Dilemma.
- A dilemma is an argument in which you claim that there
are two possible ways to go, but both have unacceptable
consequences.
- Damned if you do, damned if you don't.
- A catch-22.
- Particular absurdities which Zeno pointed out:
- If you think that motion is infinitely divisible, then you
must believe that nothing moves (the arrow).
- If you think there are many things, then Zeno points out
that you must conclude that things are both infinitely large
and infinitely small (dichotomy)
- If there are many, they must be as many as they are and
neither more nor less than that. But if they are as many as
they are, they would be limited. If there are many, things
that are are unlimited. For there are always others between
the things that are, and again others between those, and so
the things that are are unlimited. (Simplicius(a) On
Aristotle's Physics, 140.29)
- Claims that claiming there is more than one thing involves
contradiction.
- Think of birds on a telephone wire: 10 of them.
- There is no bird between bird #3 and bird #4. Zeno's
argument does not work.
- But we want to see what he meant, and this is so obvious
that he cannot have meant that!
- There is air between the birds!
- But between bird #1 and the air that touches it, there is
no thing.
- So there is an easy limit: there are 10 birds and 9 chunks
of air between them.
- But we want to see what he meant, and this is so obvious
that he cannot have meant that!
- What of points on a line?
- Between every single pair of points, there is a point half
way between them, so there are always more points!
- This works like Zeno's argument!
- But wait: how are the things in this world points?
- Are things really point-like?
- Well, no. But modern mathematicians are curious about
the points point too, and they think that in fact some
infinities are bigger than others. A man named Cantor
worked out in the 19th century a way to treat infinite
numbers as definite, believe it or not, and so Zeno's
paradox may not even apply to points on a line!
- … if it should be added to something else that exists, it
would not make it any bigger. For if it were of no size and
was added, it cannot increase in size. And so it follows
immediately that what is added is nothing. But if when it is
subtracted, the other thing is no smaller, nor is it increased
when it is added, clearly the thing being added or subtracted
is nothing. (Simplicius(a) On Aristotle's Physics,139.9)
But if it exists, each thing must have some size and
thickness, and part of it must be apart from the rest. And the
same reasoning holds concerning the part that is in front. For
that too will have size and part of it will be in front. Now
it is the same thing to say this once and to keep saying it
forever. For no such part of it will be last, nor will there
be one part not related to another. Therefore, if there are
many things, they must be both small and large; so small as
not to have size, but so large as to be unlimited. (Simplicius(a)
On Aristotle's Physics, 141.2)
- suppose there are more than one things.
- since he's just argued that things with no spatial extent do
not exist, we must suppose that at least one spatially
extended object exists.
- If spatially extended, it has a front and a back and
parts, and each part has extension too. And each part has
parts that have spatial extension, and each part of a part
of a part ...
- If you add up all those parts, you get an infinitely large
object.
- Because adding up an infinite number of objects each of
which has spatial extension yields an object of ... infinite
spatial extension!
- Right? No, wrong.
- Because there is a limit.
- 1/2+1/4+1/8+1/16 .... = (wait for it...) 1
- But now come the modern mathematicians:
- What about the series 1-1+1-1+1-1...
- You can rewrite it as (1-1)+(1-1)+(1-1)...
- And in that case, it seems that (1-1)+(1-1)+(1-1)...=0
- But then you can rewriteit as 1+
((1-1)+(1-1)+(1-1)...)=1
- Seems preposterous!
- Cauchy worked it out and said that such a series is
simply "undefined"!
- And what if Zeno were clever and said that he was not just
dividing one half in half, but rather both halves in half
each time?
- Then he would be summing up an infinite number of
equally-sized itty-bitty bits, and that sum does indeed
seems to be infinitely large.
- If we say that he has divided them into not just
itty-bitty bits, but bits so small that they have no
extension at all, then we have another problem, because
then they add up to a sum that has no extension either!
- … whenever a body is by nature divisible through and
through, whether by bisection, or generally by any method
whatever, nothing impossible will have resulted if it has
actually been divided … though perhaps nobody in fact
could so divide it.
What then will remain? A magnitude? No: that is
impossible, since then there will be something not divided,
whereas ex hypothesi the body was divisible through and
through. But if it be admitted that neither a body nor a
magnitude will remain … the body will either consist of points
(and its constituents will be without magnitude) or it will be
absolutely nothing. If the latter, then it might both
come-to-be out of nothing and exist as a composite of nothing;
and thus presumably the whole body will be nothing but an
appearance. But if it consists of points, it will not possess
any magnitude. (Aristotle On Generation and Corruption,
316a19)
- The first asserts the non-existence of motion on the ground
that that which is in locomotion must arrive at the half-way
stage before it arrives at the goal. (Aristotle Physics,
239b11)
- The [second] argument was called “Achilles,” accordingly,
from the fact that Achilles was taken [as a character] in it,
and the argument says that it is impossible for him to
overtake the tortoise when pursuing it. For in fact it is
necessary that what is to overtake [something], before
overtaking [it], first reach the limit from which what is
fleeing set forth. In [the time in] which what is pursuing
arrives at this, what is fleeing will advance a certain
interval, even if it is less than that which what is pursuing
advanced … . And in the time again in which what is pursuing
will traverse this [interval] which what is fleeing advanced,
in this time again what is fleeing will traverse some amount …
. And thus in every time in which what is pursuing will
traverse the [interval] which what is fleeing, being slower,
has already advanced, what is fleeing will also advance some
amount. (Simplicius(b) On Aristotle's Physics, 1014.10)