The Real Division in the
Court
Neither the conservative nor the liberal justices were hypocritical.
They just have fundamentally different views of federalism
by MICHAEL S. GREVE
The Weekly Standard, December 25, 2000, page 28
"So much for states' rights," Washington Post columnist E. J. Dionne
sneered in commenting on the Supreme Court's ruling in Bush v. Gore. His
comment encapsulated several weeks' worth of noisy complaints about Republican
politicians. As the Gore camp portrayed it, the GOP was cynically selling out its own
commitment to federalism when it talked trash about the Florida Supreme Court, ran to
federal court at the drop of a chad, and nationalized the appointment of presidential
electors -- a matter the Constitution explicitly reserves to the states.
Conservative Supreme Court justices, as well, were said to be hypocrites. "It is
ironic indeed," the New York Times harrumphed on the occasion of the U.S.
Supreme Court's stay of the Florida vote count, "to see the very justices who have
repeatedly ruled in favor of states' rights -- Chief Justice William Rehnquist and
Justices Antonin Scalia, Clarence Thomas, Anthony Kennedy and Sandra Day O'Connor -- do an
about-face in this case."
Conservatives could easily play this same game: Why did the New York Times not
find it "ironic" that Laurence Tribe, Gore's Supreme Court counsel, increasingly
sounds like a states' rights apostle, circa 1960? But that would be to miss a larger
point. Both liberals and conservatives actually have coherent conceptions of federalism,
and the justices pursue those conceptions with remarkable (though not unfailing)
consistency. The conservative version reflects the constitutional structure and logic. The
liberal version erodes that structure and perverts its logic.
Bush v. Gore confirms the pattern. It would be silly to deny that
partisan considerations influenced the parties' arguments before the Court, the debate
over the case, and the justices' rulings. It is true, moreover, that seven justices, the
five conservatives among them, embraced an equal protection argument that ought to worry
constitutional federalists. But the case presents no ironic inversion of federalist
positions. The parties fought, and the justices ruled, on their accustomed sides.
Two Federalisms
Every federalist system faces the challenge of ensuring national cohesion without
centralizing the entire system of government. The Founders' solution was to limit the
functions and powers of the national government, while ensuring its unqualified legal
supremacy. Within its constitutional sphere of authority, the national government must be
able to accomplish its purposes by acting directly upon the citizens, without the help or
intermediation of the states (to say nothing of obstruction by them). National laws must
have precedence over those of the states. The themes of functional separation and legal
supremacy are central to constitutional federalism. They run through the records of the
Constitutional Convention, the Federalist Papers, and the opinions of the Marshall Court.
This constitutional federalism is the federalism Clarence Thomas, Antonin Scalia, William
Rehnquist, and (with significant reservations and qualifications) Sandra Day O'Connor and
Anthony Kennedy have attempted to recapture. While their endeavor is constrained by
political realities and decades of adverse precedents, the case law is beginning to reveal
the basic contours of their federalist project.
In a series of decisions, beginning with the invalidation of the federal Gun-Free School
Zones Act in U.S. v. Lopez (1995), the five federalist justices have
reestablished constitutional limitations on the national government's power. At the same
time, a long line of cases, beginning with Seminole Tribe v. Florida
(1996), has reasserted the sovereign immunity of state governments against private
lawsuits brought under federal statutes. In Printz v. United States
(1997), the five federalists invalidated Congress's attempt to compel state and local
enforcement of federal gun control requirements. Justice Scalia's far-reaching opinion in
that case was explicitly based on the Founders' intention: If Congress wishes to coerce
citizens, it must do so directly, not by "commandeering" the states. In all
these cases, the four liberal justices (Breyer, Ginsburg, Souter, and Stevens) dissented.
In Bush v. Gore, the four liberals invoke federalism and states' rights
principally against the concurring opinion signed by Chief Justice Rehnquist and Justices
Scalia and Thomas. The concurrence finds the Florida Supreme Court's ruling in violation
of Article II of the Constitution, which provides that state legislatures shall
determine the manner of appointing presidential electors. The liberals' invocation of
federalism is misplaced, though: If the supremacy of federal law means anything, it means
that state courts may not do end-runs around the federal Constitution.
Still, one cannot dismiss the dissenters' objections as disingenuous or tactical. All four
liberal justices have invoked states' rights with some passion and regularity. Justice
Stevens in particular has been a vociferous defender of states' rights -- for example, in
cases concerning the federal preemption of state law (where the principle of federal legal
supremacy tends to push the five conservative federalists towards a
"nationalist" position).
The liberal justices, then, aren't mindless nationalists. Rather, they adhere to a
"cooperative" or "administrative" view of federalism. Under that
conception, the national government is unlimited, or at least has no constitutional
limitations that a court could recognize. It accomplishes its purposes not through legal
supremacy but through institutional cooperation with the states. The states' role lies not
in governing a separate sphere of authority but in their independent authority to
administer federal schemes.
Such a federalism is not intrinsically incoherent. It is the federalism of Germany,
Switzerland, and Europe, as Justice Breyer observed in his Printz dissent. Under
this view, there is nothing objectionable in the federal commandeering of state officers.
"The fact is that our federalism is not Europe's," Justice Scalia replied to
Justice Breyer, and as a matter of constitutional logic and structure, Scalia is right.
Cooperative federalism does, however, have a political and judicial tradition in America.
Its first judicial endorsement flowed from the pen of Justice Roger Taney, in an opinion
celebrating the state enforcement of (of all statutes) the federal Fugitive Slave Act.
Politically, cooperative federalism can be traced to the Progressives, who hoped to
harmonize national aspirations with the virtues of localism. Cooperative federalism became
dominant, both as a matter of political practice and judicial doctrine, under the New
Deal.
As the political pedigree suggests, the shift from constitutional to cooperative
federalism is tied to the growth of government. Constitutional federalism constrains
government. It limits the national government's powers, and it exposes the states, which
may wish to regulate in the vast realm beyond the national government's power, to
competitive discipline: Excessive regulation may induce productive citizens (or
businesses) to move to other, more hospitable states. Cooperative federalism, in contrast,
unleashes the national government and enables state governments, through
"cooperation" with each other and with the Congress, to establish national
policy cartels that preclude citizens from voting with their feet.
Some legal scholars have argued that the justices' seemingly wavering pro- or
anti-federalism opinions simply mask their pro- or anti-government preferences. Among the
conservative justices, however, only Clarence Thomas can reasonably be suspected of
harboring libertarian sympathies, while cooperativist Justice Breyer has inveighed in
books and articles (though not in his opinions) against the excesses of federal
regulation. The real, much deeper divide runs between constitutional constraint and
democratic aspirations, a divide that ran through the Bush v. Gore
opinions.
Constitutionalism is not per se anti-democratic. It insists that "We the People"
ordain and establish the Constitution. The constitutional point, though, is to break,
fragment, and temper democratic impulses through a system that institutionalizes
intra-governmental rivalry, jealousy, and competition. Federalism, for a prominent
example.
Democrats chafe under formalistic constraints, and they like cooperative federalism
because it trumps those constraints. When government institutions become partners rather
than competitors, they cease to frustrate the demos and instead provide it with
multiple access points. The system, to be sure, remains too messy and fragmented to
satisfy Rousseauean aspirations. Cooperative federalism, however, may be the closest
possible American approximation of the European centralizing ideal.
In the course of the post-election campaign, we have been treated to relentless appeals to
"the will of the people" -- not as expressed through the ordinary,
constitutional channels, but in the raw form of the national popular vote. The purveyors
of this demagogy opened fire on institutions that embody constitutional federalism --
prominently, the Electoral College -- and hit bottom in the persistent demands, and the
judicial attempts, to identify the voters who "intended" to vote for Gore, as
distinct from those who actually did so by complying with the formality of punching a
ballot.
When the Supreme Court's majority effectively halted the Florida Supreme Court's endeavor
to "recover," as the Florida justices put it, the voters' true intent, Justice
Ginsburg denounced the ruling as a lamentable breach with -- cooperative federalism.
Of Judges and Judging
Justice Ginsburg's operative phrase, in fairness, is "cooperative judicial
federalism," invoked twice in her dissent. Federal and state judges, no less than
elected officials, are partners in a common enterprise, and that consideration bars
federal interference with state adjudication in all but the most extreme circumstances.
Writing in the same vein, Justice Stevens took the majority to task for endorsing the Bush
plaintiffs' "lack of confidence in the impartiality and capacity" of the Florida
judges.
Putting aside the immediate causes of that distrust, it bears emphasis that the Founders
viewed state judges very much from James Baker's perspective -- as partisan, parochial
hacks. State courts would routinely favor their own citizens over those of other states,
which is why such "diversity" cases fall in the jurisdiction of federal courts.
State courts may, in the ordinary course of deciding cases, adjudicate federal causes of
action. The point of that arrangement, though, is not to empower the states but to extend
the supremacy of federal law. State court applications of federal law are subject to
Supreme Court appeal, and Congress is empowered to establish lower federal courts to
handle federal cases if state courts should prove partisan and unreliable.
The Founders considered that event quite likely. "The fitness and competency of
[state] courts should be allowed in the utmost latitude," Hamilton writes in
Federalist 81. But the conciliatory gesture is followed by an apprehension that "the
prevalency of local spirit may be found to disqualify the local tribunals for the
jurisdiction of national causes." Moreover, "state judges, holding their offices
during pleasure, or from year to year, will be too little independent to be relied upon
for an inflexible execution of the national laws."
As if to earn this distrust, the state courts of the young nation soon began to obstruct
federal laws under the guise of interpreting their own state laws. The Marshall Court
overruled them. That early case is cited as a precedent by the Bush v. Gore
majority, along with two civil rights era cases that overruled segregationist state court
decisions under state law. Justice Ginsburg's dissent acknowledges the precedents, but
proceeds to protest that Bush v. Gore "involves nothing like the
kind of recalcitrance by a state high court that warrants extraordinary action by this
Court." The Florida Supreme Court, Ginsburg writes, "surely should not be
bracketed with state high courts of the Jim Crow South."
Perhaps repeated judicial attempts to stack the deck in a presidential election do not
compare to the moral scandal of Jim Crow. But still the Florida Supreme Court made up its
own election statute, in derogation of federal law; refused to respond to the U.S. Supreme
Court's exhortation to observe the federal strictures; and then repeated the exercise.
Just how much recalcitrance is too much?
How much collateral damage, moreover, does it take until the obstruction of federal laws
and purposes, under the guise of state law interpretation, becomes a federal issue? Why,
yes, Justice Breyer concedes, "the selection of a President is of fundamental
national importance. But that importance is political, not legal." As a matter of
law, the Florida Supreme Court is entitled to drive the country over a political cliff,
and never mind Article II and statutory safe harbors.
It is entirely fitting that this position should have been urged upon the Court by David
Boies, a trial lawyer -- one of a cast of characters who round up thousands of plaintiffs
across the country, sue corporations for several billion dollars in some forsaken Alabama
county that neither the plaintiffs nor defendants have ever entered, and then protest
federal tort-reform measures on the grounds that product liability lawsuits are strictly a
matter between Alabama's citizens and judges. (The national importance is economic, not
legal, as Justice Breyer might say.) Ruthless transgressions by parochial state judges and
juries, however, were not the Founders' idea of federalism. They were the Founders'
nightmare.
The Sovereign
Having extolled cooperative federalism, Justice Ginsburg ends her disquisition on Article
II by invoking the real, constitutional federalism. The concurring justices'
"solicitude for the Florida Legislature comes at the expense of the more fundamental
solicitude we owe to the legislature's sovereign," meaning the citizens and the State
of Florida as a political entity. "Were the [conservative] members of this Court as
mindful as they generally are of our system of dual federalism," Justice Ginsburg
chastises, "they would affirm the judgment of the Florida Supreme Court."
The serious, almost persuasive version of this argument is that the remedy for the Florida
court's transgressions lay with the Florida legislature, rather than the U.S. Supreme
Court. But that is not Justice Ginsburg's argument. The only hint at the Florida
legislature's powers appears in the majority's per curiam opinion, not in Ginsburg's or in
any other dissent. With that omission, Ginsburg's solicitude for state sovereignty
collapses into an alarming embrace of judicial supremacy.
In its two decisions, the Florida Supreme Court trashed an entire structure of government.
It emasculated canvassing boards by subjecting their determinations to de novo
judicial review (excepting the boards that had manufactured additional Gore votes, which
the court ordered to be certified without any review). The court twice overruled perfectly
sensible determinations by the secretary of state (one made pursuant to established state
law; the other, pursuant to the Florida Supreme Court's own deadline). The court twice
supplanted the legislature's election laws with its own rules and deadlines.
A comparable legal action by the Florida legislature, the U.S. Supreme Court learned from
Boies during oral argument, would have constituted an impermissible postelection change of
the laws; coming as it did from the Florida Supreme Court, it constituted mere
"interpretation." When the Florida legislature threatened to exercise its
rightful authority to appoint a slate of electors, democratic (and Democratic) partisans
hysterically denounced the attempt as -- well, an undemocratic interference with the
judiciary's recovery of the voters' true intentions. Nothing and no one, no rule and no
structure, must stand between the will of the people and its vicarious interpretation by
the judicial committee for public safety.
That is the sovereign to whom, in the dissenting Supreme Court justices' world,
we owe solicitude and unquestioning obedience. "It is confidence in the men and women
who administer the judicial system," Justice Stevens writes, "that is the true
backbone of the rule of law."
The rule of law is in trouble, and Bush v. Gore provides little comfort.
The justices' unanimous remand of the Florida Supreme Court's first ruling expressed
concern over the state court's reckless disregard for Article II and the federal safe
harbor provisions. In the end, though, only three justices were prepared to follow the
constitutional argument, while seven members of the Court resorted to an unprecedented,
free-floating equal protection argument that invites federal regimentation for almost any
reason.
One may hope that the equal protection part of Bush v. Gore will prove a
ticket for this day and train only. The deeper and true problem is the assault on
constitutionalism. That assault reflects long-rampant misconceptions, and it comes itself
in the constitutionalist garb of federalism, judicial restraint, and the rule of law. For
that reason, it cannot be countered with facile slogans about "judicial
activism," "states' rights," and the like. We will have to remind ourselves
of some long-forgotten truths about what it means to live in a constitutional, federal
republic. If the crisis just passed helps us to do so, it will have done some good.
Michael S. Greve is the John G. Searle Scholar at the American Enterprise Institute
and director of AEI's Federalism Project. He is the author of Real Federalism: Why It
Matters, How It Could Happen (AEI, 1999).